The Role of Wisdom in Technological Age
Wisdom is concept commonly referred to in regular
conversation and speech. But what really
does one mean when one refers to wisdom?
Are current generations “wiser” than earlier ones due to our greater
access to information, or our superior scientific and technical knowledge?
The famous economist E.F Schumacher is one who argues
against this view of wisdom, in fact he seems to separate the concept of wisdom
from scientific knowledge with the following statement:
“The maps produced by modern materialist scientism leave all
the questions that really matter unanswered.
More than that, they do not even show the way to a possible answer: they
deny the validity of the questions. The situation was desperate enough in my
youth half a century ago; it is even worse now because the ever more rigorous
application of the scientific method to all subjects and disciplines has
destroyed even the last remnant of ancient wisdom – at least in the Western
world” (Schumacher 1977; pg 13)
In this statement Schumacher refers to “ancient wisdom”
suggesting that something has been lost. Note, that Schumacher does not attack the
scientific method itself, but does appear to distinguish wisdom from mere
know-how. In this regard he himself quotes Dr Victor Frankl who states:
“The present danger does not really lie in the loss of
universality on the part of the scientist, but rather in his pretence and claim
of totality …”
In relation to this Schumacher states that:
“[People] long for guidance on how to live as responsible
human-beings and are told that they are machines, like computers, without free
will and therefore without responsibility”.
In this respect, Schumacher’s rejection of humans as
machines is somewhat reminiscent of the arguments of Penrose (1989) which we look
briefly at in another lesson.
Perhaps the distinction Schumacher is drawing between wisdom
and knowledge can be better understood by reference to his earlier book “Small
is Beautiful” (see Note 1).
“ [… ] scientists never tire of telling us that the fruits
of their labours are ‘neutral’: whether they enrich humanity or destroy it
depends on how they are used. And who is to decide how they are used? There is
nothing in the training of scientists and engineers to enable them to take such
decisions, or else, what becomes of the neutrality of science?” (Schumacher,
1974; pg 86).
The neutrality of science claim is analogous to the common
claim today that technology is not good or bad, it depends on how it is used
(just do a Google search to verify how common this claim is).
Schumacher continues on to say:
“Science and engineering produce ‘know-how’; but ‘know-how
is nothing by itself; it is a means without an end, a mere potentiality, an
unfinished sentence. “Know-how’ is no more a culture than a piano is music.”
(Schumacher, 1974; pg 86)
So perhaps wisdom is what we use to guide our decisions on
how to apply our knowledge? In this
case, Schumacher (1974) goes on to discuss whether or not learning the
humanities can provide people with the appropriate ‘training’ to decide on how
to (and whether to) apply new technology. In this sense he suggests that
education can assist us in making these decisions. In short, he suggests that
philosophy and meta-physics play a key role in dealing with these questions:
“[…] philosophy has been defined as the love of, and seeking
after, wisdom. Socrates said: ‘Wonder is the feeling of philosophy, and
philosophy begins with wonder […] no god is a philosopher or seeker after
wisdom for he is wise already. Neither do the ignorant seek after wisdom; for
herein is the evil of ignorance, that he who is neither good nor wise is
nevertheless satisfied with himself’” (Schumacher, 1977; pg 15).
Schumacher then quotes as follows:
“a philosophy comprehensive enough to embrace the whole of
knowledge is indispensable” (Schumacher 1977, pg 16)
Thus we appear to have wisdom (philosophy) sitting
metaphorically ‘above’ knowledge and encompassing it.
Schumacher (1977) includes a criticism of recent European
philosophers. He singles out Descartes
(1595-1650) as a particularly influential philosopher in this regard and quotes
Descartes:
“’Those who seek the direct road to truth should not bother
with any object of which they cannot have a certainty equal to the
demonstrations of arithmetic and geometry’” (pg 17)
This claim is very much at odds with the ideas of
Schumacher, who argues that questions concerning uncertainty are of critical
interest for humanity. He also quotes Descartes
on a tenant of his philosophy which we know now to be particularly vulnerable
on at least two fronts. The quote is as follows in relation to his proposed
method of reasoning. Descartes proposal is to:
“reduce involved and obscure propositions step by step to
those that are simpler, and then, starting with the intuitive apprehension of
all those that are absolutely simple, attempt to ascend to the knowledge of all
others by precisely similar steps”.
The criticism now made by Schumacher of this philosophical
approach is perhaps more apparent in today’s world than in Descartes
period. Schumacher declares Descartes’
approach “frighteningly narrow” as Descartes excludes all knowledge and ideas
that are not precise and certain.
However, even if we take this narrow philosophy we can easily identify
the two vulnerabilities alluded to above.
The first is that despite claiming to be a system of rational reasoning,
at its most fundamental level this system relies on one’s intuition (“intuitive
apprehension”). Descartes relies here on
the simplicity of the propositions, however, history has shown that even simple
propositions that are apparently obvious can be wrong. A famous example of this is Euclid’s
postulate that two parallel lines can never cross (Lewis 1920). This was
accepted by mathematicians for over two thousand years as ‘intuitively obvious’
until it was found to be incorrect when applied in the domain of quantum
mechanics (it turns out Euclid’s assumption only applies in the special case of
a plane, it does not apply to hyper planes).
The second vulnerability arises from Gödel’s theorem, which is discussed
in detail in another lesson. Gödel’s theorem raises the possibility that a
system, such as that proposed by Descartes, may not allow one to ascend to
knowledge in the way that Descartes claims, and in fact may allow one to ascend
to knowledge that is internally inconsistent. However, it seems that in the
final analysis Descartes and Schumacher are interested in two entirely
different things. Descartes interest is
primarily that humankind should become “masters and possessors of nature” (pg
18) whilst Schumacher is more interested in values for guiding human decision
making. These differences in purpose appear to shade the perspective of each. Perhaps
a crude characterisation of the two can be provided by considering a continuum
ranging from practical knowledge at one end to meta-physics at the other. On
this scale Descartes may be closer to the practical end whilst Schumacher
appears closer to the meta-physical end. Schumacher also regards meta-physical
knowledge as ‘higher’ than practical knowledge, in the sense that the use of
practical knowledge is subordinate to and guided by higher knowledge (or
wisdom). At the practical end of the
scale we focus more on what can we do
(or how do things work in the realm
of science). While Schumacher is more
interested in higher (meta-level) moral and value questions such as what should we do? Schumacher suggests
that just because we can do something, that does not necessarily mean that we
should.
In relation to the proper role of philosophy, Schumacher
(1977) quotes Etienne Gilson:
“It is its permanent duty to order and regulate an ever
wider area of scientific knowledge, and to judge ever more complex problems of
human conduct; it is its never-ending task to keep the old sciences in their
natural limits, to assign their places, and their limits, to the new sciences;
last, not least, to keep all human activities, however changing their circumstances,
under the sway of the same reason by which man alone remains the judge of his
own works and, after God, the master of his own destiny.” (pg 20).
Schumacher seems to believe philosophy provides us with a
path to wisdom and should guide us in relation to our goals. What these goals
are is again a philosophical question and he proposes that traditional wisdom provides the following answer:
“Man’s happiness is to move higher, to develop his highest
faculties, to gain knowledge of the higher and highest things”.
Schumacher’s arguments are echoed in many more recent
criticisms in relation to technology, for example, Jensen and Draffan (2004)
make the following statement as an assessment of the state of science in the
absence of higher-level regulation as suggested by Schumacher:
“What does
science do? It calls for everything to be measured. It calls for everything
that cannot be measured to be ignored or destroyed" (pg 73)
Winner (1992) also comments on this theme, but on the poorly
controlled and directed application of technology:
“[…] a continuing and ever-accelerating process of technical
innovation in all spheres of life, which brings with it numerous ‘unintended’
and uncontrolled consequences in nature and society […] the same technologies
that have extended man’s control over the world are themselves difficult to
control. Recognition of this fact is not limited to the critics of
technological society. It extends to the most highly developed sectors of big
technology where the science of cybernetics and an obsession with ‘command and
control’ have been responses to internal difficulties of this sort.” (pp
28-29)
I will continue build on these themes around the role of
science and technology in society in later posts.
References
Jensen, D & Draffan, G 2004, Welcome to the Machine: Science,
Surveillance, and the Culture of Control, Chelsea Green Publishing,
Vermont, USA.
Lewis, FP 1920, ‘History of the
Parallel Postulate’, The American Mathematical Monthly, vol. 27, No. 1,
pp 16–23. Available from: doi:10.2307/2973238, JSTOR 2973238.
Penrose, R 1989, The
Emperor’s New Mind, Oxford University Press.
Schumacher, EF 1977, A
Guide for the Perplexed, Abacus.
Winner, L 1992, Autonomous
Technology: Technics-out-of-control as a Theme in Political Thought, The
MIT Press.
Note 1: rated as one of the top 100 most influential books written since
WWII by the Times Book Review: ‘The hundred most
influential books since the war.’, 1995, The
Times Literary Supplement, October 6, p. 39.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
Subscribe to Post Comments [Atom]
<< Home